by David Abram
from
Gaia Website
The Gaia hypothesis, if
taken seriously, has logical implications that call into question
the mechanical model of perception upon which most contemporary
scientific discourse is based. These implications reach beyond the
separate sciences and begin to influence our ordinary perceptual
experience. To view Gaia as an entirely objective entity only
trivialized the radical nature of the hypothesis.
The Gaia hypothesis, as formulated by geochemist James Lovelock,
represents a unique moment in scientific thought: the first glimpse,
from within the domain of pure and precise science, that this planet
might best be described as a coherent, living entity. The hypothesis
itself arose in an attempt to make sense of certain anomalous
aspects of the Earth’s atmosphere. It suggests that the actual
stability of the atmosphere, given a chemical composition very far
from equilibrium, can best be understood by assuming that the
atmosphere is actively and sensitively maintained by the oceans, the
soils, the plants, and the creatures -- indeed, by the whole of the
biosphere. In Lovelock’s own words, the hypothesis that,
the entire range of living matter on
Earth, from whales to viruses,
and from oaks to algae, could be regarded as constituting a single
living entity, capable of manipulating the Earth’s atmosphere to
suit its overall needs and endowed with faculties and powers far
beyond those of its constituent parts.
It is gratifying to see that this hypothesis is slowly gaining a
hearing in the scientific world, while being further substantiated
by biologist Lynn Margulis, whose meticulous research on microbial
evolution has already shown the existence of certain Gaian
regulatory systems. That the hypothesis will gain proponents only
slowly is to be expected, for to accept it as valid is to throw into
question many deeply ingrained scientific and cultural assumptions.
In fact the recognition of Gaia has powerful implications for
virtually every realm of scientific and philosophical endeavor,
since it calls for a new way of perceiving our world. In this essay
I will explore just a few implications of the Gaia hypothesis for
our understanding of perception itself.
Our Immersion in Gaia
It is significant that the first evidence that the surface of this
planet functions as a living entity should come from a study of the
atmosphere, the very aspect of the Earth that we most commonly
forget. The air is so close to us that we tend to leave it out of
our thinking entirely -- much as we do not often attend to the
experience of breathing, an act so essential to our existence that
we take it for granted. The air that surrounds us is invisible to
our eyes; doubtless this has something to do with why we usually act
and speak as though there were nothing there. We refer to the space
between things, or the space between two people; we do not speak of
the air between us, or the air between oneself and a nearby tree. We
generally assume, unless we stop to think about it, that the space
between us is roughly continuous with the space between planets.
This is attested by our everyday language -- we say that we dwell on
the Earth, not that we live within the Earth. Yet if the
Gaia
hypothesis is correct, we shall have to admit that we exist in this
planet rather than on it. In direct contradiction to the earlier
scientific assumption that life on Earth’s surface is surrounded by
and adapts to an essentially random environment, Gaia indicates that
the atmosphere in which we live and think is itself a dynamic
extension of the planetary surface, a functioning organ of the
Earth.
It may be that the new emphasis it places on the atmosphere of this
world is the most radical aspect of the Gaia hypothesis. For it
carries the implication that before we as individuals can begin to
recognize the Earth as a self-sustaining organic presence, we must
remember and reacquaint ourselves with the very medium within which
we move. The air can no longer be confused with mere negative
presence or with the absence of solid things: Henceforth the air is
itself a density-- mysterious, indeed, for its invisibility -- but a
thick and tactile presence nonetheless. We are immersed in its
depths as surely as fish are immersed in the sea. It is the Medium,
the silent interlocutor of all our musings and moods. We simply
cannot exist without its support and nourishment--without its vital
participation in whatever we are up to at any moment.
In concert with the other animals, with the plants, and with the
microbes themselves, we are an active part of the Earth’s
atmosphere, constantly circulating the breath of this planet through
our bodies and brains, exchanging certain vital gasses for others,
and thus monitoring and maintaining the delicate make-up of the
medium. As Lovelock has indicated, the methane produced by the
microorganisms that make their home in our digestive tracts -- the gas
we produce in our guts -- may conceivably be one of our essential
contributions to the dynamic stability of the atmosphere (less
important, to be sure, than the methane contribution of ruminant
animals, but essential nonetheless). Small wonder that we of
literate culture continue to forget the air, this ubiquitous
presence, for we prefer to think of ourselves serving a loftier
"purpose," set apart from the rest of creation. Our
creativity, we assume, resides not in the depths of our flesh but in
some elevated realm of pure thoughts and ideas that stands somehow
outside the organic.
Yet it is only by remembering the air that we may recover a place in
the real world we inhabit. For the air is the invisible presence, so
little understood, that materially involves us in the internal life
of all that we see when we step out of doors, in the hawks and the
trees, in the soil and the sea and the clouds. Let us return to this
point later. For now it is enough to discern that the Gaia
hypothesis implicates the enveloping atmosphere as a functioning
part of the overall system. Thus, if we choose to view this planet
as a coherent, self-sensing auto-poietic entity, we shall have to
admit that we are, ourselves, circumscribed by this entity. If
Gaia exists, then we are inside her.
Our Perception of Gaia
The consequences for our understanding of perception and the
function of the human senses are important and far reaching.
Traditionally perception has been taken to be a strictly one-way
process whereby value-free data from the surrounding environment is
collected and organized by the human organism. Just as biologists
had until recently assumed, for simplicity's sake, that life adapts
to an essentially random environment, so psychologists have
assumed that the senses are passive mechanisms adapted to an
environment of random, chance events. The interior human "mind" or
"subject" is kept apprised of these random happenings in the
exterior "objective" world by the sense organs, mechanical
structures that register whatever discrete bits of sensory
data--bits of light, sound, pressure--they come into contact with,
and transfer these separate bits of information into the nervous
system. Here these separate sensations are built up, step by step,
into a representation of the external world. It is this internal
representation that is ultimately viewed and given meaning by the
innermost "mind" of the perceiver.
Such is the classic model of perception propounded by Locke,
Descartes and Berkely in the seventeenth century, and later
formalized by the founders of modern scientific psychology.
Although it has undergone many revisions and qualifications, this
account still underlies most of the scientific discourse of our
time. Within this account, "meaning" and "value" are assumed to be
secondary, derivative phenomena resulting from the internal
association of external facts that have no meaning in themselves.
And the external world is tacitly assumed to be a collection of
purely objective, random things entirely lacking in value or meaning
until organized by the ineffable human mind. If this sounds like the
assumption behind the agenda of today’s "value-free"
sciences, we
should note that each of the natural sciences completely depends, at
some level, upon the exercise of human perception for the
accumulation of its data -- whether through a microscope, a telescope,
or even the keyboard and screen of a computer. Yet none of the
separate sciences has ever come up with an alternative description
of perception that could supplant the traditional account. (Even
quantum physicists, who have long recognized the untenability of
this description of perception with regard to the sub-atomic domain,
have proposed no substantial alternative.)
Each of the contemporary sciences, then, must still pay lip service
to a model of perception constructed in accordance with
seventeenth-century notions of the mechanical nature of the physical
world and the absolute separation of mind from matter. One important
reason for our prolonged adherence to an obsolete model may be the
fact that, although it does not describe perception as we actually
experience it, this model does describe perception as we need to
conceive it if we are to continue in our cultural program of natural
manipulation and environmental spoilage without hindrance of ethical
restraint. The traditional account of perception as a uni-directional
mechanical process is the only account possible if we still assert
the convenient separation of psyche, subjectivity, or
self-organization from the material world that surrounds us.
The Gaia hypothesis immediately suggests an alternative view of
perception. For by explicitly showing that self-organization is a
property of the surrounding biosphere, Gaia shifts the locus of
creativity from the human intellect to the enveloping world itself. The creation of meaning, value, and purpose is no
longer accomplished by a ghostly subject hovering inside the human
physiology. For these things - value, purpose, meaning - already abound
in the surrounding landscape. The organic world is now filled with
its own meanings, its own syntheses and creative transformations.
The cacophony of weeds growing in an "empty" lot is now recognized
for its essential, almost intelligent role in the planetary
homeostasis, and now even a mudflat has its own mysteries akin to
those of the human organism. We begin to glimpse something of the
uncanny coherence of enveloping nature, a secret meaningfulness too
often obscured by our abstractions. This wild proliferation is not a
random chaos but a coherent community of forms, an expressive
universe that moves according to a diverse logic very different from
that logic we attempt to impose. But if, following the Gaia
hypothesis, we can no longer define perceptions as the intake of
disparate information from a mute and random environment, what then
can we say that perception is?
The answer is surprisingly simple: Perception is communication. It
is the constant, ongoing communication between this organism that I
am and the vast organic entity of which I am apart. In more
classical terms, perception is the experience of communication
between the individual microcosm and the planetary macrocosm.
Let us think about this for a moment. If the perceivable environment
is not simply a collection of separable structures and accidental
events; if, rather, the whole of this environment taken together
with myself constitutes a coherent living Being "endowed with
faculties and powers far beyond those of its constituent parts,"
then everything I see, everything I hear is bringing me information
regarding the internal state of another living entity -- the
planet itself. Or rather about an entity that is both other and not-other,
for as we have seen, I am entirely circumscribed by this entity, and
am, indeed, one of its constituent parts. Perhaps it is misleading,
then, to use the term "communication" to describe a situation in
which one of the communicants is entirely a part of the other. The
word communication, so often associated with a purely linguistic
interchange, has overtones of something rather more conscious and
willful than what we are trying to describe. Here we are referring
to an exchange far more primordial, and far more constant, than
that verbal exchange we carry on among ourselves. What is important
is that we describe it as an exchange, no longer a one-way transfer
of random data from an inert world into the human mind but a
reciprocal interaction between two living presences -- my own body and
the vast body of the biosphere. Perhaps the term "communion" is more
precise than "communication." For by communion we refer to a deeper
mode of communication, more corporeal than intellectual, a sort of
sensuous immersion--a communication without words.
Perception, then -- the whole play of the senses -- is a
constant
communion between ourselves and the living world that encompasses
us.
Recent Studies of Perception
Such a description of perception, as a reciprocal phenomenon
organized as much by the surrounding world as by oneself, is not
entirely new to contemporary psychology. Indeed, recent developments
in the study of perception indicate that sooner or later it must be reconceptualized as an interactive phenomenon. For example, research
on the evolutionary development of perceptual systems in various
species suggests that these systems simply cannot be understood in
isolation from the communication systems of those species. And at
least two of the most important twentieth century investigators
working (independently of each other) on the psychology of human
perception -- Maurice Merleau-Ponty in France and James J. Gibson in
the United States -- had already begun, decades ago, to speak of the
surrounding physical worlds as an active participant in our
perceptual experience.
J.J. Gibson and "Direct Perception"
Jamse J. Gibson published his text The Perception of the Visual
World in 1950 and followed it with The Senses Considered as
Perceptual Systems in 1966 and The Ecological Aproach to Visual
Perception in 1979. In these books Gibson challenged the
traditional account of perception, which as I indicated above,
describes perception as an internal process whereby an initially
meaningless mass of sensory data (resulting, say, from the
impingement of photons on the retinal nerve cells) is built up into
an internal representation of the external world. This account, true
to its Cartesian foundations, assumes a fundamental disjunction
between the psychological (human) perceiver, described ultimately in
mentalistic terms, and the purely passive environment, described in
terms borrowed from physics. Gibson called this entire paradigm into
question by asserting that perception must be studied as an
attribute of an organism and its environment taken together. He
showed that if we assume a natural compatibility between an animal
and its environment -- what he and his followers refer to as an
"animal-environment synergy" -- then perception is recognized not as
an indirect process carried out inside the organism but a direct
exchange between the organism and its world.
Gibson felt that artificial laboratory situations had misled
psychologists into conceptualizing perception as a physically
passive, internal, cerebral event. He believed that new researchers
studying perception should not construct artificially isolated and
static experimental conditions that have nothing to do with
everyday life -- instead they should strive to approximate natural
conditions. If they did so they would come to understand the senses
not as passive mechanisms receiving valueless data but as active,
exploratory systems attuned to dynamic meanings already there in the
environment. These dynamic meanings, or "affordances" as
Gibson has
called them, are the way specific regions of the environment
directly address themselves to particular species or individuals.
Thus, to a human maple tree may afford "looking at" or "sitting
under," while to a sparrow it affords "perching," and to a squirrel
it affords "climbing." But these values are not found inside the
minds of the animals. Rather they are dynamic, addressive properties
of the physical landscape itself when the landscape is comprehended
in a manner that does not artificially separate it from the life of
the various organisms that inhabit it and contribute to its
continuing evolution.
In short, for Gibson and those who carry on Gibson’s work (the
"direct perceptionists") perception is elucidated as a
reciprocal
interchange between the living intentions of any animal and the
dynamic affordances of this world. The psyche, as studied by these
psychologists, is a property of the ecosystem as a whole.
Merleau-Ponty and "the Primacy of Perception"
Maurice Merleau-Ponty had already come to some very analogous
conclusions in his major study, The Phenomenology of Perception,
published in France in 1945. He did not seek to build a finished
theory of perception but simply to attend as closely as possible to
the experience of perception and to describe it afresh. In doing so
he steadfastly refuses to construct an explicit system which we
might reify into yet another frozen concept, another "internal
representation" to set between ourselves and our environment.
Instead he seeks a language, a way of speaking that will not sever
our living bond with the world.
One of the major accomplishments of his Phenomenology was to show
that the fluid creativity we commonly associate with the human
intellect is, in actuality, an elaboration or recapitulation of a
deep creativity already underway at the most immediate level of
bodily experience. For Merleau-Ponty, it is the body -- the organic,
sensitive body itself -- that perceives the world and, ultimately,
thinks the world -- not some interior and immaterial mind. Through an
intricate and lucid analysis, Merleau-Ponty slowly discloses
perception as an almost magical activity in which what he calls the
"lived-body" orients and responds to the active solicitations of the
sensory world, a sort of conversation carried on beneath all our
speaking between the body and the gesturing, sounding landscape it
inhabits. In numerous later essays, Merleau-Ponty disclosed this
perceptual "pact" between body and world as the very foundation of
truth in history, in political thought and action, in art, and in
science.
In the book on which he was working at the time of his early death
in 1962 -- published posthumously, in an unfinished form, as The
Visible and the Invisible -- Merleau-Ponty took up this earlier
analysis of perception and carried it a step further, seeking to
describe experientially the actual world to which our senses give us
entry, the common domain that we investigate with our reason and
science. He found that the "invisible" in man -- the region of thought
and ideality -- is inextricably intertwined with the shifting,
metamorphic, intelligent nature of the enveloping world. If
perception gives way in us to thought and reflective awareness, these
are not properties closed within the human brain, but are the human
body’s open reply to questions continually put to it by the subtle
self-organizing character of the natural environment.
Merleau-Ponty’s thought is far too complex and elusive to be
summarize here. Yet I believe it is possible to experience
Merleau-Ponty’s radical undoing of the traditional "mind-body
problem" simply by dropping the conviction that one’s mind is
anything other than the body itself. If one is successful in this
then one may abruptly experience oneself in an entirely new
manner -- not as an immaterial intelligence inhabiting an alien,
mechanical body, but as a magic, self-sensing form -- a body that is
itself awake and aware, from its toes to its fingers to its tongue
and its ears--a thoughtful and self-reflective animate presence.
(This corresponds, roughly, to the first stage in Merleau-Ponty’s
investigation -- the period of the Phenomenology of Perception.) Yet
if one maintains this new awareness for a duration of time, becoming
comfortable enough with it to move about without losing the
awareness, one will being to experience a corresponding shift in
the physical environment. Birds, trees, even rivers and stones begin
to stand forth as living, communicative presences.
For when my intelligence does not conceive of itself as something
apart from the material body but starts to recognize its grounding
in these senses and this flesh, then it can no longer hold itself
apart from the natural world in which this body has its place. As
soon as my awareness forfeits its claim to a total transcendence and
acknowledges its inherence in this physical form, then the whole of
the physical world shudders and wakes... This experience corresponds
to the second, unfinished phase in Merleau-Ponty’s writing, when he
refers less often to the body as the locus of perceptual
experienced and begins to write of the collective "Flesh," his term
for the animate, sensitive existence that encompasses us (of which
our own sentient bodies are but a part).
Thus Merleau-Ponty, who in his earlier work had disclosed the
radically incarnate nature of awareness and intelligence, ends by
elucidating the world itself from the point of view of the
intelligent body -- as a wild, self-creative, thoroughly animate macrocosmos.
Perception is now understood as the "Chiasm," the
continuous intertwining between one’s own flesh and "the Flesh of
the World."
So both Gibson and Merleau-Ponty, pursuing two different styles of
analysis inherited from their respective intellectual traditions,
arrive at an alternative understanding of perception
not as a
cerebral event but as a direct and reciprocal interchange between
the organism and its world. While Gibson’s followers strive to map
this interchange in precise, systematic theorems, Merleau-Ponty
sought a new language which could ground the various disciplines in
an awareness of perception as radical participation. In doing so he
began to uncover, hidden behind our abstractions, a sense of the
Earth as a vast, inexhaustible entity, the forgotten ground of all
our thoughts and sensations.
These two steps toward a post-Cartesian epistemology are remarkably
consonant with the Gaia hypothesis and the implication that
perception itself is a communication or communion
between an
organism and the living biosphere.
Reconsidering Perception
Still, we must further clarify our Gaian definition of perception by
answering two obvious objections. Some may object that it is
meaningless to speak of perception as a direct communion between
oneself and the planetary macrocosm, since in many situations one’s
senses are directly engaged only in relation to another individual
organism -- as when one is simply talking with another person.
Furthermore, even when one is perceptually attuned to many different
phenomena at once -- when, for example, one is hiking through a
forest -- still one’s senses are then interwoven within a single
specific region of the planet, a "bioregion" or
ecosystem that has
its own internal coherence distinct from the planet as a whole.
Therefore, if perception is a communion it is at best a communion
with relative wholes within Gaia.
But this is merely a provisional objection. We may certainly define
specific regions or worlds within Gaia as long as we acknowledge
Gaia’s presence behind these. For if Lovelock’s hypothesis proves
correct, then it is the overall planetary metabolism that lends
organic coherence to the myriad systems or wholes within it. A
forest ecosystem is one such whole. A human ecosystem or culture is
another, ad when conversing among ourselves we are directly involved
in the whole linguistic culture that provides the language for our
exchange.
A closer look at perception is also called for at this point.
Traditional research on perception has sought to study each sense as
a separate and exclusive modality. Merleau-Ponty, however, has shown
that in immediate experience perception is a thoroughly synaesthetic
phenomenon. In everyday life, in other words, the so-called
"separate" senses are thoroughly blended and intertwined, and it is
only in abstract reflection, or in the psychologist’s laboratory,
that we are able to isolate the various senses from one another. For
example, when I perceive the waves that are breaking on the shore
below my cabin, there is no separation of the sound of those waves
from what I see of them. The swell of each wave as it rolls toward
me, the tumbling crash of those waters before they sweep across the
beach, only to hiss back down, overturning all the pebbles, to meet
the next vortex -- these are experiences in which visual, aural, and
visceral tactile modalities all envelope and inform each other. A
certain ocean smell, as well, permeates the whole exchange, lending
it an unmistakable flavor.
Very little is known about the mysterious chemical senses of smell
and taste. Within any textbook of perception it is difficult to find
more than a few pages devoted to these senses, which seem to resist
objective measurement and analysis. Yet it is with these subtle
senses that we perceive the state of the very medium in which we
move. We both smell and "taste" the atmosphere in the course of our
breathing, and these sensations are so constant, so necessary, and
yet so unconscious (or unattended to) that we may truly say they
provide the hidden context for all the rest of our perceiving. And
as Lovelock’s work indicates, the atmosphere is a complex but
thoroughly integrated phenomenon, perhaps the most global of all the
Earth’s attributes. As I become more aware that this organism I am
not only perceives things through the atmosphere but also perceives
the atmosphere itself -- that I constantly smell, taste, and touch the
atmosphere as well as hear it rustling in the leaves and see it
billowing the clouds -- I will come to realize the extent to which my
senses do indeed keep me in direct and intimate contact with the
life of the biosphere as a whole.
A second important objection to
our ecological view of ordinary perception as a continuous communion
with the Earth will come from those who point out that there is much
we perceive that is not of this planet -- the other planets, the moon,
the stars, and our own star, the sun. While obviously not unfounded,
this objection still rests on the assumption that we dwell upon the
surface of an essentially inert planet. Yet if we recognize Gaia as
a self-regulating entity, we must recognize the enveloping
atmosphere as a part of that entity. All that we know of other
worlds reaches us via the rich and swirling atmosphere of our own
world, filtered through the living lens of Earth’s sky. Even when we
consider the dependence of vision on the radiant light of the sun,
we must acknowledge that the sunlight we know is entirely
conditioned by the air that envelops and is a part of the living
biosphere.
While Gaia depends on the sun for its nourishment, we
depend on Gaia. If we venture beyond the edges of its atmosphere it
is the living Earth that enables us to do so: We go in vehicles made
of Earth and filled up with Earth’s sky -- we need this in order to
live. This, I believe, is the deeper significance of James
Lovelock’s ideas concerning what he calls the "terraformation" of
other planets. By contemplating how humanity might someday transfer
the complex Gaian metabolism to other planets in order to make them
habitable by human life, Lovelock is underscoring the fact that
neither humanity nor any other species we know can exist outside the
incredibly complex Terran metabolism of which our own bodies and
minds are an internal expression -- if we wish to colonize other
worlds we shall have to bring this metabolism with us. We are
entirely a part of the life that envelops this planet, and thus the
living Earth as a whole is the constant intermediary between
ourselves and the rest of the universe.
Our senses never outstrip the conditions of the living world, for
they are the very embodiment of those conditions. Perception, we
must realize, is more an attribute of the biosphere than the
possession of any single species within it. The strange, echo
locating sensory systems of bats and of whales, the subtle heat-sensors of snakes, the electroreception of certain fish and the
magnetic field sensitivity of migratory birds are not random
alternatives to our own range of senses -- rather they are necessary
adjuncts of our own sensitivity, born in response to variant aspects
of a single harmonious whole.
Once perception is understood in this light, as interaction and
exchange, as communion and deep communication, then several of the
puzzles which haunt contemporary psychology will begin to resolve
themselves. For instance, the notion of "extra-sensory perception,"
itself a contradiction in terms, may be recognized as the necessary
by-product of the contemporary assumption that ordinary perception
is an entirely mechanical phenomenon. If we assume that the senses
are merely passive mechanisms geared to an environment of random,
chance events, then any experience of direct, non-verbal
communication with others will inevitably be construed as a bizarre
event that takes place in some extraordinary dimension outside the
material world. But what if the living body, when healthy, is in
constant communication with the space that surrounds it? What if the
senses are not passive mechanisms but active, exploratory organs
evolved in the depths of a living environment?
We have only to
consider the amount of chemical information regarding the shifting
internal state of an organism that is continually exhaled, expelled,
and secreted into the ambient air -- information that may be picked
up, intentionally or unintentionally, by the chemical senses of any
nearby organism -- to realize the extent to which a form of subtle
communication may be carried on between our bodies at an entirely prereflective level. In a like manner our eyes and our ears are
capable of discriminations far more subtle than those to which we
normally attend. When these organs are taken together with organs of
taste, smell and touch, as interactive components of a single synaesthetic perceptual system, we may discern that the
living body
is a natural clairvoyant, and that extra-sensory perception
is not
extrasensory at all.
Perception as Communion
The concept of a living biosphere enveloping the Earth provides a
condition for the resolution of numerous theoretical dilemmas. I
have focused, in this article, on the paradox engendered by the
assumption that, within the physical world, awareness is an
exclusively human attribute. If the external world exists only
according to mechanical laws of determinacy and chance, what then is
the point of contact between such a determinate world and human
awareness -- in other words what is perception? I have suggested that
in fact the external world is not devoid of awareness -- that it is
made up of numerous subjective experiences besides those of our
single species -- and furthermore that those myriad forms of biotic
experience, human and non-human, may collectively constitute a
coherent global experience, or life, that is not without its own
creativity and sentience.
If such is the case, as the evidence for Gaia attests, then
perception is no longer a paradox, for there is not the total
disjunction between "inside" and "outside" worlds that was
previously assumed. Just as the external world is subject to similar
methods of study--as the burgeoning field of neurology attests.
But the reverse is also true. Just as the interior world of our
psychological experience has many qualities that are ambiguous and
indeterminate, so the external world now discloses its own
indeterminacy and subjectivity -- its own interiority, so to speak.
Perception, then, is simply the communion and deep communication
between our own organic intelligence and the creativity that
surrounds us.
A recognition of the perceptual ramifications of the Gaia hypothesis
is, I believe, essential to any genuine appraisal of the hypothesis.
Without an awareness of Gaia as this very world, which we engage not
only with our scientific instruments but with our eyes, our ears,
our noses and our skin -- without the subjective discovery of Gaia as
a sensory, perceptual, and psychological power -- we are apt to
understand Lovelock’s discovery in exclusively bio-chemical terms,
as yet another scientific abstraction, suitable for manipulating and
engineering to fit our purposes.
Lovelock himself, in his most recent speculations regarding the
exportation of Gaia to the surface of Mars, seems oblivious to the
psychological ramifications of Gaia. The idea that the
living
biosphere, once discovered, can be mechanically transferred, by and
for humans, to another planet, overlooks the extent to which Gaia
calls into question the instrumental relation which we currently
maintain with our world. Recognizing Gaia from within, as a
psychological presence, greatly constrains the extent to which we
can consciously alter and manipulate the life of this planet for our
own ends.
As I have attempted to show, the discovery of a unitary,
self-regulating biosphere, if accepted, completely undermines the
classical account of perception upon which each of the separate
sciences, until now, has been based. If our senses, our perceptions,
and our whole manner of thinking have taken shape in reciprocal co-evolution and communion with a coherent living biosphere, then in
all probability it is our own Earth whose traces we actually
discover in our most abstract investigations of quantum and
astronomical spaces, the living Earth peering back at us through all
our equations. For until we have recognized perceptually our organic embeddedness in the collective life of the biosphere -- until we have
realigned our thoughts with our senses and our embodied situation -- any
perception of other worlds must remain hopelessly distorted.
The theoretical discourse of our time has largely alienated us from
the world of our everyday senses, while accustoming us to speak
casually of the most far-flung realities. Thus other galaxies,
"black holes," the birth of the universe, the origins of space and
of time, all seem quite matter-of-fact phenomena easily encompassed
by the marvelous human mind. But Gaia, as a reality that
encompasses us, a phenomenon we are immediately in and of, suggests
the inconsistency of such blackboard abstractions. Gaia is no mere
formula -- it is our own body, our flesh and our blood, the wind
blowing past our ears and the hawks wheeling overhead. Understood
thus with the senses, recognized from within, Gaia is far vaster,
far more mysterious and eternal than anything we may ever hope to
fathom.
I have suggested that the most radical element of the Gaia
hypothesis, as presently formulated, may be the importance that it
places on the air, the renewed awareness it brings us of the
atmosphere itself as a thick and mysterious phenomenon no less
influential for its invisibility. In Native American cosmology, the
air or the Wind is the most sacred of powers. If it is the invisible
principle that circulates both within us and around us, animating
the thoughts of all breathing things as it moves the swaying trees
and the clouds. And indeed, in countless human languages the words
for spirit or psyche are derived from the same root as the words for
the wind and breath. Thus in English the word "spirit" is related to
the word "respiration" through their common origin in the in the
Latin word "spiritus," meaning "breath." Likewise our word "psyche,"
with all its recent derivations, has its roots in the ancient Greek
"psychein," which means "to breath" or "to blow (like the wind)."
If we were to consult some hypothetical future human about the real
meaning of the word "spirit," he might reply as follows:
Spirit, as any post-industrial soul will tell you, is simply another
word for the air, the wind, or the
breath. The atmosphere is psyche
of this world. And all our perceiving, the secret work of our eyes,
our nostrils, our ears and our skin, is our constant communication
and communion with the life of the whole. Just as, in breathing, we
contribute to the ongoing life of the atmosphere, so also in seeing,
in listening, in real touching and tasting we participate in the
evolution of the living textures and colors that surround us, and
thus lend our imaginations to the tasting and shaping of the Earth.
Of course the spiders are doing this just as well...
|